Research Article


DOI :10.26650/arcp.1284749   IUP :10.26650/arcp.1284749    Full Text (PDF)

Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time

Ahmet Alperen Can

Aristotle characterized time as a number because he considered the earlier, later, and now being units associated with motion. In this context, the present study investigates time within the Peripatetic natural philosophy and the framework of numbered motion. However, time is a continuous quantity in the system, while numbers are discontinuous. For this reason, the concept of numbers in the definition is seen to have created the problem of discontinuity regarding questions such as how to understand time as a number, the requirement of a counting soul and relation to plurality. In fact, Aristotle accepted time as number in the sense that it is counted because it is continuous. Hellenistic commentators also tried rationalization of time as a number. The basic claim of this article is that Avicenna’s conception of time is a reconstructed version of the Aristotelian conceptualization of time. By distinguishing between the continuous and discontinuous relationships among quantities, Avicenna established time as a conceptualized quantity that can be considered both as a magnitude and a measure. Accordingly, Avicenna considered time itself is continuous due to magnitude being continuous, with numbers being added to time as accidents. In additional, he considered time to not necessitate a counting soul in terms of magnitude. This article examines Avicenna’s reconstruction of the concept of time through the use of number, magnitude, continuity, and celestial spheres.

DOI :10.26650/arcp.1284749   IUP :10.26650/arcp.1284749    Full Text (PDF)

İbn Sînâ’nın Aristotelesçi Zaman Kavramını Yorumlaması

Ahmet Alperen Can

Aristoteles, zamanı harekette açığa çıkan öncelik ile sonralıktan ve ânın birimler hâlinde düşünülmesinden dolayı sayı olarak betimlemiştir. Bu bağlamda Peripatetik doğa felsefesinde zaman, hareketin sayılması çerçevesinde tartışılmıştır. Halbuki bu sistemde zaman sürekli, sayı süreksiz niceliktir. Dolayısıyla tanım cümlesindeki sayı kavramı; zamanın sayı olmasının nasıl anlaşılacağı, sayının bir sayanı gerektirmesi ve çokluklarla ilişkili olması gibi hususlarda süreksizlik sorununu meydana getirmiştir. Nitekim Aristoteles, sürekli olması dolayısıyla zamanı, sayılan anlamında sayı kabul eder. Helenistik şârihler de zamanın sayı formunda betimlenmesinde, nicelikler arasında süreklilik ve süreksizlik geçişkenliğini çözmeye çalışmıştır. Bu makalenin ana iddiası, İbn Sînâ’nın zaman anlayışının, Aristotelesçi zaman kavrayışının yeniden yapılandırılmış versiyonu olduğudur. İbn Sînâ zamanı, nicelikler arasındaki sürekli– süreksiz ilişkisine karşı, öncelikle hem büyüklük hem de ölçü olarak tartışılabilen miktar kavramıyla kurar. İbn Sînâ’ya göre miktar sürekli olduğundan, zaman bizzat süreklidir; sayı ise arazî biçimde zamana eklenir. Ayrıca, miktar olması bakımından zaman, sayan nefsi zorunlu kılmaz. Bu makale, İbn Sînâ’nın zaman kavramında gerçekleştirdiği yeniden yapılandırmasını; sayı, miktar, süreklilik ve göksel küreler üzerinden incelemektedir. 


EXTENDED ABSTRACT


Determining the similarities and differences that occurred between Avicenna and Aristotle is an important study method in the literature on the history of philosophy. In this context, Avicenna can be examined both as an Aristotelian and as an original philosopher by considering his Kitāb al-Shifā [Book of Healing]. This is also true regarding Avicenna’s view of time. Recent research on time has argued Avicenna to have defined time as a magnitude rather than a number. In particular, many texts are found to argue that Avicenna had established the nature of time based on the concept of magnitude. However, the concept of number also held a central position in his understanding of time. Therefore, the claim that Avicenna had perceived time solely as a magnitude is a challenging one. As a result, the concepts of magnitude, measure, and number as existed in Avicenna’s understanding of time also need to be considered. Whether a hierarchical relationship exists between time as a magnitude and time as a number is also worth investigating.

While Aristotle had tried to determine the nature of time through its relation to movement, he also sought ways to think of it in terms of units. Aristotle depicted the concepts of priority and posteriority to symbolize the continuity of movement. However, the use of the concept of numbers in the definition of time created the problem of discontinuity regarding categories. In this context, Avicenna’s way of constructing the concept of time can be interpreted as a restructuring by applying Aristotle’s arguments to different contexts in order to eliminate the discontinuity.

Aristotle introduced the conceptualization of time as a continuously counted entity in order to resolve the problem of continuity for numbers with time. However, Avicenna did not include the idea that time is a number in the sense of being counted in his definition. now was the understanding of time in Avicenna’s philosophy built upon the concept of numbers. Avicenna is seen to have presented an ambivalent view of the concept of time, which he had based on the concepts of magnitude and numbers. According to the philosopher, however, the former is essential while the latter represents the accidental aspect of time. While numbers constitute one aspect of time, magnitude constitutes another more important aspect of time and is the cause of the qualities that time has.

Avicenna made many different arrangements regarding the concept of time. The most important of these was the interpretation of Aristotle’s claim that there is no time when there is no soul counting through Avicenna’s use of celestial spheres and circular motion. Time performs the act of measurement through the continuity provided by cyclical motion. Therefore, time does not require a counting soul in order to exist. The celestial sphere that is the cause of the existence of time moves because of the soul, and that same soul is the perfection of the form of the celestial sphere. Although it does not have the same close causal relationship with the counting soul, the relationship Avicenna established between the soul and time can be understood in this manner.

In Avicenna’s system, numbers are replaced by magnitude, thereby downplaying the emphasis that Aristotle and Hellenistic commentators had placed on time being a number in the sense of being counted. According to Avicenna, the attachment of a discontinuous quantity to a continuous quantity is bilaterally possible. In fact, time itself is continuous in terms of quantity. Consequently, motion encompasses both numbers and magnitude, both of which are referred to as time; however, numbers correspond to the accidental aspect of time, whereas magnitude denotes its quantity. The continuity of motion and time is ensured by celestial motion, thus enabling the measurement of other motions. Therefore, Avicenna’s interpretation of the concept of time aimed to explain that attaching illusory discontinuities such as month, year, and day to time does not make it inherently discontinuous. Therefore, this study has examined the claim that adding a discontinuity to time does not make time discontinuous.


PDF View

References

  • Aristoteles, Fizik, çev. Saffet Babür, İstanbul: Yapı Kredi Yayınları, 2019. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, Gökyüzü Üzerine, cev. Saffet Babur, Ankara: BilgeSu Yayıncılık, 2013. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, Kategoriler, cev. Y. Gurur Sev, İstanbul: Pinhan Yayıncılık, 2019. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, Metafizik, çev. Y. Gurur Sev, İstanbul: Pinhan Yayıncılık, 2019. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, Physics, çev. Roben Waterfield, New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, Ruh Üzerine, çev. Zeki Özcan, Ankara: Sentez Yayıncılık, 2014. google scholar
  • Aristoteles, et-Tabî’a, cev. İshak b. Huneyn, haz. Abdurrahman Bedevi, Mısır: y.y., 1974. google scholar
  • Dağ, M., “İslâm Felsefesinde Aristocu Zaman Görüşü”, Ankara Üniversitesi İlâhiyat Fakültesi Dergisi, 1973, c. XIX, s. 105. google scholar
  • Fârâbî, Kitâbu’l-Hurûf, çev. Omer Turker, İstanbul: Türkiye Yazma Eserler Kurumu Yayınları, 2015. google scholar
  • Güven, Ö., “Aristoteles’in Sayı Anlayışı” Kutadgubilig 34, 2017, 383-395. google scholar
  • Irâkî, Â., el-FelsefetÜt-tabîiyye ‘inde İbn Sînâ, Kahire: y.y., 1969. google scholar
  • İbn Bâcce, Şerhu’s-simâ: Aristoteles’in Fizik Şerhi, çev. C. Şenel, A. Taibi, İstanbul: Dergâh Yayınları, 2022. google scholar
  • İbn Meymûn, Delâletu’l-Hâirîn, çev. Osman Bayder, Özcan Akdağ, İstanbul: Albaraka Yayınları, 2021. google scholar
  • İbn Rüşd, el-Cevâmi‘ fi’l-felsefe: Kitâbu’s-Simâü’t-tabî‘î, ed. Josep Puig; thk. A. Zimmermann, S. G. Nogales, Madrid: Instituto Hispana- Arabe de Cultura, 1983. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Fizik, çev. Muhittin Macit, Ferruh Özpilavcı, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2014. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Fizik II, çev. Muhittin Macit, Ferruh Özpilavcı, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2005. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, ‘Uyûnü’l-hikme, haz. Abdurrahman Bedevî, Beyrut: Dâru’l-kalem, 1980. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, İşaretler ve Tembihler, cev. Muhittin Macit, Ali Durusoy, Ekrem Demirli, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2013. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Kategoriler, cev. Muhittin Macit, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2010. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Metafizik, cev. Ekrem Demirli, Omer Turker, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2013. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Metafizik II, cev. Ekrem Demirli, Omer Turker, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2013. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, en-Necât: Felsefenin Temel Konuları, cev. Kubra Senel, İstanbul: Dergah Yayınları, 2018. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: Oluş ve Bozuluş, cev. Muammer İskenderoglu, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2008. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: es-Simâü’t-tabî‘î, nşr. Saîd Zâyid, İbrâhim Medkûr, Kahire: el-İdâretü’l-‘Âmme li’s-Sekâfe, 1983. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’t-Talîkât, nşr. H. M. el-Âbîdî, Kum: Mektebetu’l-rlami’l-Islamf, 1981. google scholar
  • İbn Sînâ, Kitâbu’ş-Şifâ: İkinci Analitikler, çev. Ömer Türker, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2014. google scholar
  • Kindî, “Beş Terim Üzerine”, Felsefî Risâleler, cev. Mahmut Kaya, İstanbul: Klasik Yayınları, 2014. google scholar
  • Lammer, A., The Elements ofAvicenna’s Physics, Berlin: DeGruyter, 2018. google scholar
  • Lear, J. Aristoteles: Anlama Arzusu, çev. Ayşegül Yurdaçalış, İlknur Urkun Kelso, İstanbul: Alfa Yayınları, 2020. google scholar
  • Macit, M., İbn Sînâ’da Doğa Felsefesi ve Meşşâî Gelenekteki Yeri, İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık, 2013. google scholar
  • McGinnis, J. “Ibn Sina? on the Now: Text and Commentary” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, S. 73/1, 1999, s. 73-106. google scholar
  • McGinnis, J., “The Topology of Time: An Analysis of Medieval Islamic Accounts of Discrete and Continuous Time” The Modern Schoolman, 2003, 81(1), s. 5-25. google scholar
  • McGinnis, J., Time and Time Again: A Study of Aristotle and Ibn Sina’ Temporal Theories, Doktora Tezi, Philadelphia University, 1999. google scholar
  • Muhammed, A., Tasavvuru İbn Sînâ lî’z-zaman ve usûlihi’l-Yunâniyye, İskenderiye: Dâr’ül-Vefâ li’dünyâ el-tibâ ve’l-neşr, 2003. google scholar
  • Philoponus, J., On Aristotle Physics 4.10-14, çev. Sarah Broadie, Great Britain: Bloomsbury, 2011. google scholar
  • Râzî, F., el-Mebâhisü’l-Meşrikıyye fî ilmi’l-ilâhiyyât ve’t-tabî’iyyât, c. I, nşr. Muhammed Bağdâdî, Beyrut: Dârü’l-kitâbi’l-Arabî, 1990. google scholar
  • Ross, D., Aristoteles, cev. Ahmet Arslan, Istanbul: Kabalcı Yayıncılık, 2011. google scholar
  • Shayegan, Y., Avicenna on Time, Doktora Tezi, Harvard Üniversitesi, 1986. google scholar
  • Simplicius, On Aristotle Physics 4.1-5 and 10-14, cev. J. O. Urmson, Great Britain: Bloomsbury, 1992. google scholar

Citations

Copy and paste a formatted citation or use one of the options to export in your chosen format


EXPORT



APA

Can, A.A. (2023). Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time. Archives of Philosophy, 0(58), 135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


AMA

Can A A. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time. Archives of Philosophy. 2023;0(58):135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


ABNT

Can, A.A. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time. Archives of Philosophy, [Publisher Location], v. 0, n. 58, p. 135-158, 2023.


Chicago: Author-Date Style

Can, Ahmet Alperen,. 2023. “Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time.” Archives of Philosophy 0, no. 58: 135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


Chicago: Humanities Style

Can, Ahmet Alperen,. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time.” Archives of Philosophy 0, no. 58 (May. 2024): 135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


Harvard: Australian Style

Can, AA 2023, 'Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time', Archives of Philosophy, vol. 0, no. 58, pp. 135-158, viewed 19 May. 2024, https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


Harvard: Author-Date Style

Can, A.A. (2023) ‘Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time’, Archives of Philosophy, 0(58), pp. 135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749 (19 May. 2024).


MLA

Can, Ahmet Alperen,. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time.” Archives of Philosophy, vol. 0, no. 58, 2023, pp. 135-158. [Database Container], https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749


Vancouver

Can AA. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time. Archives of Philosophy [Internet]. 19 May. 2024 [cited 19 May. 2024];0(58):135-158. Available from: https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749 doi: 10.26650/arcp.1284749


ISNAD

Can, AhmetAlperen. Avicenna’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Concept of Time”. Archives of Philosophy 0/58 (May. 2024): 135-158. https://doi.org/10.26650/arcp.1284749



TIMELINE


Submitted17.04.2023
Accepted09.06.2023
Published Online26.06.2023

LICENCE


Attribution-NonCommercial (CC BY-NC)

This license lets others remix, tweak, and build upon your work non-commercially, and although their new works must also acknowledge you and be non-commercial, they don’t have to license their derivative works on the same terms.


SHARE




Istanbul University Press aims to contribute to the dissemination of ever growing scientific knowledge through publication of high quality scientific journals and books in accordance with the international publishing standards and ethics. Istanbul University Press follows an open access, non-commercial, scholarly publishing.