Research Article


DOI :10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005   IUP :10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005    Full Text (PDF)

From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory

Aylin Kılıç Cepdibi

It would probably not be wrong to say that the 20th century was the most terrifying in human history. What made this century especially terrifying is not only the fact that its means of destruction reached a level of power beyond the imagination of its manufacturers, but also the experience of totalitarianism, which radically destroyed all institutions and structures shaped by mankind for centuries. Hannah Arendt’s work The Origins of Totalitarianism strikingly reveals that the origins that make Nazi totalitarianism new and unprecedented are, in fact, “right now happening” in the world. These constructions, relations, and situations that continue in the form of “undercurrent”—as Arendt calls it—did not die out with the defeat of Nazism. Here the idea of “human condition,” which constitutes the second part of Arendt’s investigation, makes the phenomenological analysis of three forms of activity that underlie it. One of the most important theses of Arendt’s work is that there exists a dramatic relationship between the process of conquest of all human relation by the principle of utilitarianism and instrumentalism, which motivates all work and production, and the social climate in which totalitarian regimes can be shaped. In this study, we will examine how the human condition, i.e., homo faber, and the utilitarian principle—in which totalitarian domination can come into existence— in Arendt’s political theory may result in instrumentalization and gradually make the whole world seem worthless. We will also try to explain how these events form favorable conditions for the total domination of people. 

DOI :10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005   IUP :10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005    Full Text (PDF)

Homo Faber’in Dünyasından Animal Laborans’ın Zaferine: Hannah Arendt’in Politika Teorisinde Totaliter Tahakkümün Vücut Bulduğu İnsanlık Koşulu Üzerine Bir İnceleme

Aylin Kılıç Cepdibi

20. yüzyıla insanlık tarihi içinde en dehşet verici yüzyıl demek herhalde yanlış olmayacaktır. Ne var ki bu yüzyılı dehşet verici kılan, yalnızca yıkım araçlarının, onları imal edenlerin tahayyülünün de ötesine geçebilecek bir güce ulaşmış olması değil, insanlığın yüzyıllar boyunca evrilerek şekillendirdiği ve şekillendiği tüm kurumları ve yapıları yok edici bir radikalliğe sahip olan totalitarizm deneyimidir. Hannah Arendt’in “Totalitarizmin Kaynakları” isimli eseri, Nazi totalitarizmini yeni ve emsalsiz kılan niteliği oluşturan unsurların kökenlerinin aslında sırada dünyada “şimdi” olup biten şeyler olduğunu çarpıcı bir biçimde ortaya koyar. Arendt’in deyimiyle “dip akıntısı” şeklinde devam eden bu yapılar, ilişkiler ve durumlar Nazizm’in yenilgisiyle de ortadan kalkmış değildir. Arendt’in kökenlere yönelik incelemelerinin ikinci bölümünü oluşturan yetkin eseri “İnsanlık Durumu”, insanlık durumunun temelini oluşturan üç etkinlik biçiminin fenomenolojik çözümlemesini yapar. Eserinde en önemli iddialardan biri, bu etkinlikler içerisinde “homo faber”in etkinliği olan “yapmanın”, onun tüm iş ve imalatının güdüleyici ilkesi olan “faydacılığının” ve “araçsallık” ölçütünün tüm beşeri ilişkileri sarıp sarmalaması süreci ile totaliter yönetim biçimlerinin şekillenebileceği toplumsal iklim arasında önemli bir ilişki bulunmaktadır. Bu çalışmada, Arendt’in politika teorisinde totaliter tahakkümün vücut bulabildiği “insanlık durumu”, “homo faber” ve onun egemenliğindeki “faydacı” ilkenin nasıl sonunda kendisini de içine alarak bütün dünyanın ve yeryüzünün araçsallaştırılması ve giderek değersizleştirilmesiyle sonuçlandığı, bunun ise totaliter tahakkümün aradığı insanlık koşulu olduğu açıklanmaya çalışılacaktır. 


EXTENDED ABSTRACT


Claiming that the 20th century was the most terrifying in human history would probably not be wrong. Yet, what made this century so terrifying was that not only did its means of destruction reach a power beyond the imagination of those who fabricated them, but also the fact that totalitarianism radically destroyed all former institutions and structures that had evolved and shaped humanity for centuries. Hannah Arendt’s work The Origins of Totalitarianism is one of the most sophisticated studies that strikingly reveal the origins that characterize Nazi totalitarianism. What appears to be new and surprising, she contends, are in fact “present” in our ordinary world. These structures, relations, and situations that continue in the form of “subterranean streams” were not removed with the defeat of Nazism. In this context, it is almost inevitable to reflect upon the origins and investigate the “elements” and “conditions” that allowed totalitarianism to be made “possible,” as the experience of totalitarianism—which in itself is unique and cannot be explained “directly” by any idea or fact of the past—broke all connections and traditions of the Western world. I believe Arendt offers a multi-faceted view of totalitarianism. On the one hand, she explores the human “condition” which allows “totalitarian domination” to emerge. In other words, she explores the conditions in which humanity faced such forms of domination. On the other hand, in association with the former, she describes the relationship between human condition and totalitarian domination. In her later writings, she also points out the conditions of humanity after the experience of totalitarianism. What she proposes is a new way of thinking about the “thoughtlessness” that is “the heedless recklessness or hopeless confusion,” and how this has become the most prominent feature of modern humanity. For such a reason, Arendt states: “It is nothing more than to think about what we are doing.”

The powerful work that constitutes the second part of Arendt’s research, The Human Condition, gives a phenomenological analysis of three forms of activity that underlie the human condition: (i) “labor,” corresponding to the biological life of humans as animals; (ii) “work,” corresponding to the artificial world of objects that people build; and (iii) “action” or “praxis,” corresponding to individual pluralism. One of the most important conclusions that can be drawn from reading this work is the relation between “doing,” i.e., the activity of homo faber, and the processes of “utilitarianism” and “instrumentality,” i.e., the motivating principles of all work and production. This is done in order to wrap up all human relations, and to create a social climate under which totalitarian forms of governance may emerge. It appears possible to detect the existence of such a relationship. However, the conditions of totalitarian governance cannot solely be explained by the world and philosophy of homo faber. When all of Arendt’s works are examined, the “instrumentality” of homo faber includes activities such as “planning” and “accounting,” which have been used extensively in bureaucratic processes of totalitarian rule. Yet, at the same time Arendt’s observations of the world of animal laborans manifest humans as feeling more “useless” or “homeless” and reminds us of people under totalitarian domination, especially those in “concentration camps” (even though the “living corpses” in the camps indicate a radicalized version of this state). Moreover, we are aware that everything is “planned” to eliminate any kind of “thinking” activity in our daily lives or in the concentration camps. In this case, it would not be wrong to say that we are confronted with a regime that has “considered” every subtle detail to ensure complete obedience of its “citizens” (by destroying all meanings the word itself implies), and the destruction of all thinking ability. There exists a kind of “uselessness” and “loneliness” where traces of the life of animal laborans on community level can be found, while a full reason for homo faber working among the administration and the bureaucratic staff (even there, everyone can easily be relocated or exterminated, except the Führer!). One of the most striking and tragic feature of Arendt’s work on the world of animal laborans is that it sheds light on what happens in today’s postcapitalist world. On the one hand, “consumer society” is based on the “utilitarian” mind that drives all kinds of human relations and actions—and its individual who mobilizes the activity of “thinking,” according to the instrumentality of homo faber only to meet the needs of “making a living” and “consuming”—belong to the “world of necessities” but are simultaneously alienated from the world. On the other hand, “modern science,” which has gained power beyond what was ever imagined, functions in a manner that is alienating and moving away from public discourse. Arendt regards these processes as totalitarian qualities that continue to exist in the modern world “now” and “here” as subterranean streams.

A society made up of consumers cannot “know how to take care of a world and the things belongs to the space of worldly appearances” because the attitudes of consumption that are valid in society “spells ruin everything it touches.” The collapse of the public sphere, the only area where a common sense of well-being can emerge, brings with it the loss of reality to the human mind. If “reality is what is seen and heard by everybody” we cannot talk about common reality in a form where such union cannot exist. Instead, we may have to think that every sophisticated thing can be true, or that nothing can be true or real. In a life where permanence is abolished, Arendt points out how the desire for immortality has become an empty ambition. She further argues “modern man, when he lost the certainty of a world to come, was thrown back upon himself and not upon this world; far from believing that the world might be potentially immortal, he was not even sure that it was real.” We cannot know whether scientific and technological developments after Arendt indicate that the world is also mortal (and this would be a source of consolation) or whether it is a valid excuse for humans who try to forget the evanescence of life (with the frenzy of consumption in the form of hedonistic philosophy). Nevertheless, Arendt’s thesis for this new human condition is extremely tragic, as only the consumer who is able to spend his labor can maintain his family life. What remains of the human who is thrown back upon himself is the motives of the body directed to the passions devoid of meaning? And, if there is an ultimate goal, this is the power of the life cycle to maintain the permanence of human species. Individual life has become part of this cycle. Animal laborans is not only immediately under the urgency of meeting the necessity of life, but also alienated from all the anxieties and sensitivities that do not emerge directly by the course of life. 

It is precisely the environment where the human is homeless, i.e., insecure. An individual not without a place in divine order, nature, or history, has a longing to find himself “at home” as opposed to being alienated. This desire and longing is precisely what can be employed through totalitarian ideologies. However, because of the absence of a world, they have established together through word and action, the individuals, who are isolated from each other, believe that they have overcome the suffering of homelessness through the supremacy of totalitarian ideology, and in turn become practitioners of the worst of schemes in the world. Whether through a party or state over the whole society, what distinguishes the power of totality and totalitarianism from dictatorship or absolutism is the ideologies. In this context, totalitarianism is never the power of a single person or a group, but at the same time, it is the power of a doctrine, of an ideology whether it allegedly implements the laws of either nature or history, or of what is being regarded as the “truth.” For citizens and for Haw political institutions—which provide relative reliance to the public and political world by their persistence over individual mortality, which in turn are expected to resist this totalitarian wave and to defeat it—it is impossible to stand out against this domination, if they have lost the ground that make them citizens and institutions. For this reason, it is the human conditions, which a totalitarian domination seeks to find, include citizens who have lost their ability to distinguish fact from fiction, and right from wrong, and the institutions that have lost their constitutional grounds and human action to protect them.


PDF View

References

  • Arendt, H. (1994). Essays in understanding. New York, NY: Schocken Books. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (1995). Men in dark times. London, UK: Harcourt Brace & Company. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2003). Some questions on moral philosophy. In J. Kohn (Ed.), Responsibility and judgement (pp. 49–148). New York, NY: Schocken Books. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2005). Socrates. In J. Kohn (Ed.), The promise of politics (pp. 5–40). New York, NY: Schocken Books. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2007). The moral of history. In J. Kohn & R. H. Feldman (Eds.), The Jewish writings (pp. 312–316). New York, NY: Schocken Books. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2009). Kötülüğün sıradanlığı (Adolf Eichmann Kudüs’te) (Ö. Çelik, Çev.). İstanbul: Metis Yayınları. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2014a). Geçmişle gelecek arasında (B. S. Şener & O. E. Kara, Çev.). İstanbul: İletişim Yayınları. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2014b). Örgütlü suç ve evrensel sorumluluk. J. Kohn (Ed.), Formasyon, sürgün, totalitarizm, anlama denemeleri 1930-1954 içinde (s. 190–204, İ. Yıldız, Çev.). Ankara: Dipnot Yayınları. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2014b). Sosyal bilim teknikleri ve toplama kamplarına dair incelemeler. J. Kohn (Ed.), Formasyon, sürgün, totalitarizm, anlama denemeleri 1930-1954 içinde (s. 330–349, İ. Yıldız, Çev.). Ankara: Dipnot Yayınları. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2014b). Totalitarizmin doğası üzerine. J. Kohn (Ed.), Formasyon, sürgün, totalitarizm anlama denemeleri 1930-1954 içinde (s. 450–492, İ. Yıldız, Çev.). Ankara, Dipnot Yayınları. google scholar
  • Arendt, H. (2016). İnsanlık durumu (B. S. Şener, Çev., 8. basım). İstanbul: İletişim Yayınları. google scholar
  • Bauman, Z. (1997). Modernite ve holocaust (S. Sertabipoğlu, Çev.). İstanbul: Sarmal Yayınları. google scholar
  • Benhabib, S. (1996). The reluctant modernism of Hannah Arendt. California: Sage. google scholar
  • Berktay, F. (2012). Dünyayı bugünde sevmek (Hannah Arendt’in politika anlayışı). İstanbul: Metis Yayınları. google scholar
  • Cambridge Dictionary. (2017). Mistake. Retrieved from http://dictionary.cambridge.org/tr/ s%C3%B6zl%C3%BCk/ingilizce/mistake google scholar
  • Canovan, M. (1978). The contradictions of Hannah Arendt’s political thought. Political Theory, 6(1), 5–26. google scholar
  • Canovan, M. (1995). Hannah Arendt: A reinterpretation of her political thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. google scholar
  • Çoban, F. (2010). Emek’ten eylem’e: Hannah Arendt. H. O. İnce (Ed.), Günümüzde yeni siyasal yaklaşımlar içinde (s. 92–137). Ankara: Doğu-Batı Yayınları. google scholar
  • Comte-Sponville, A. (2004). Büyük erdemler risalesi (I. Ergüden, Çev.). İstanbul: İstanbul Bilgi Üniversitesi Yayınları. google scholar
  • Gambetti, Z. (2007). Marx ve Arendt: Emek, iş, eylem üzerinden üç siyaset biçimi. Birikim, 217, 46–54. google scholar
  • Hegel, W. F. (1986). Tinin görüngübilimi (A. Yardımlı, Çev.). İstanbul: İdea Yayınları. google scholar
  • Kateb, G. (1983). Hannah Arendt: Politics, conscience, evil. New Jersey, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld. google scholar
  • Levin, M. (1979). On animal laborans and homo politicus in Hannah Arendt. Political Theory, 7(4), 521–531. google scholar
  • Lodziak, C. (2003). İhtiyaçların manipülasyonu: Kapitalizm ve kültür (B. Kurt, Çev.). İstanbul: Çitlembik Yayınevi. google scholar
  • Lukes, S. (2006). Bireycilik (İ. Serin, Çev.). İstanbul: Bilim ve Sanat Yayınları. Marx, K. (1986). 1844 felsefe yazıları (M. Belge, Çev.). Ankara: V Yayınları. google scholar
  • Montaigne. (1987). Denemeler (S. Eyuboğlu, Çev.). İstanbul: Cem Yayınevi. google scholar
  • Montesquieu. (1998). Kanunları ruhu üzerine (F. Baldaş, Çev., 2. basım). İstanbul: Toplumsal Dönüşüm Yayınları. NTV. (2017). Dünyayı 100 yıl içerisinde terk etmeliyiz. http://www.ntv.com.tr/galeri/teknoloji/ stephen-hawking-dunyayi-100-yil-icerisinde-terk-etmeliyiz,W33 GvSjN0CBaMoHDZ9kHQ/ Cc6v2pJI3UKsdB1ms98hyA adresinden edinilmiştir. google scholar
  • Ollman, B. (2015). Yabancılaşma (Marx’ın kapitalist toplumdaki insan anlayışı) (A. Kars, Çev., 2. basım). İstanbul: Yordam Yayınları. google scholar
  • Platon. (1986). Protagoras. Diyaloglar içinde (C. 2, s. 123–175, T. Gökçöl, Çev.). İstanbul: Rezmi Kitabevi. google scholar
  • Platon. (1986). Theaitetos. Diyaloglar içinde (C. 2, s. 181–270, M. Gökberk, Çev.). İstanbul: Remzi Kitabevi. google scholar
  • Sezer, D. (2013). Hannah Arendt. A. Tunçel & K. Gülenç (Ed.), Siyaset felsefesi tarihi (Platon’dan Zizek’e) içinde (s. 638–676). Ankara: Doğu-Batı Yayınları. google scholar
  • Türk Dil Kurumu. (2017). Hata. http://www.tdk.gov.tr/index.php?option=com_gts&view=gts adresinden edilmiştir. google scholar
  • Wolin, S. (2016). Politics and visions (exp. Ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press. google scholar
  • Wood, E. M. (2008). Kapitalizm demokrasiye karşı (Tarihsel maddeciliğin yeniden yorumlanması) (Ş. Artan, Çev.). İstanbul: Yordam Yayınları. google scholar
  • Yavuz, E. (2016). Stephen Hawking: İnsanoğlu’nun 1000 yıldan az ömrü kaldı. Cumhuriyet Gazetesi. http://www.cumhuriyet.com.tr/haber/dunya/631264/Stephen_Hawking__insanoglu_ nun_1000_yildan_az_omru_kaldi.html adresinden edinilmiştir. google scholar
  • Yazıcıoğlu, S. (2009). Anlam yitimi olarak şiddet. S. Yazıcıoğlu (Ed.), Doğumunun 100. yılında Hannah Arendt içinde. İstanbul: YKY. google scholar
  • Yenişehirliğoğlu, Ş. (1995). Birey toplum devlet ilişkileri. Ankara: Ümit Yayıncılık. google scholar

Citations

Copy and paste a formatted citation or use one of the options to export in your chosen format


EXPORT



APA

Kılıç Cepdibi, A. (2018). From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory. Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences, 27(1), 69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


AMA

Kılıç Cepdibi A. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory. Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences. 2018;27(1):69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


ABNT

Kılıç Cepdibi, A. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory. Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences, [Publisher Location], v. 27, n. 1, p. 69-93, 2018.


Chicago: Author-Date Style

Kılıç Cepdibi, Aylin,. 2018. “From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory.” Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences 27, no. 1: 69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


Chicago: Humanities Style

Kılıç Cepdibi, Aylin,. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory.” Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences 27, no. 1 (May. 2025): 69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


Harvard: Australian Style

Kılıç Cepdibi, A 2018, 'From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory', Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences, vol. 27, no. 1, pp. 69-93, viewed 1 May. 2025, https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


Harvard: Author-Date Style

Kılıç Cepdibi, A. (2018) ‘From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory’, Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences, 27(1), pp. 69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005 (1 May. 2025).


MLA

Kılıç Cepdibi, Aylin,. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory.” Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences, vol. 27, no. 1, 2018, pp. 69-93. [Database Container], https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


Vancouver

Kılıç Cepdibi A. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory. Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences [Internet]. 1 May. 2025 [cited 1 May. 2025];27(1):69-93. Available from: https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005 doi: 10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005


ISNAD

Kılıç Cepdibi, Aylin. From The World of Homo Faber to The Victory of Animal Laborans: An Analysis of the Human Condition in Which Totalitarian Domination Can Come into Existence in Arendt’s Political Theory”. Siyasal: Journal of Political Sciences 27/1 (May. 2025): 69-93. https://doi.org/10.26650/siyasal.2017.27.1.0005



TIMELINE


Submitted24.10.2017
Accepted29.03.2018

LICENCE


Attribution-NonCommercial (CC BY-NC)

This license lets others remix, tweak, and build upon your work non-commercially, and although their new works must also acknowledge you and be non-commercial, they don’t have to license their derivative works on the same terms.


SHARE




Istanbul University Press aims to contribute to the dissemination of ever growing scientific knowledge through publication of high quality scientific journals and books in accordance with the international publishing standards and ethics. Istanbul University Press follows an open access, non-commercial, scholarly publishing.